106
|
DEVELOPMENT OF JURISPRUDENCE
| |
The agreement of al-Madina had weight with Malik ibn Anas. The agreement of many
divines and legists always had weight of a kind. Among lawyers, a principle, to the
contrary of which the memory of man ran not, had been determining. But this was wider, and
from this time on the unity of Islam was assured. The evident voice of the People of
Muhammad was to be the voice of God. Yet this principle, if full of hope and value for the
future, involved the canonists of the time in no small difficulties. Was it conceivable
that the agreement could override the usage of the Prophet? Evidently not. There must,
then, they argued, once have existed some tradition to the same effect as the agreement,
although it had now been lost. Some such lost authority must be presupposed. This can
remind us of nothing so much as of the theory of the inerrant but lost original of the
Scriptures. And it had the fate of that theory. The weight of necessity forced aside any
such trifling and the position was frankly admitted that the agreement of the community
was a safer and more certain basis than traditions from the Prophet. Traditions were
alleged to that effect. "My People will never agree in an error," declared
Muhammad, or, at least, the later church made him so declare.
But ash-Shafi'i found that even the addition of agreement to Qur'an and Prophetic usage
did not give him basis enough for his system. Opinion he utterly rejected; the preference
of Abu Hanifa and the conception of the common welfare of Malik ibn Anas were alike to
him. It is true also that both had been practically saved under agreement. But
|
|
ANALOGY; THE FOUR SOURCES
|
107 | |
he held fast by analogy, whether based on the Qur'an or on the usage of the Prophet. It
was an essential instrument for his purpose. As was said, "The laws of the Qur'an and
of the usage are limited; the possible cases are unlimited; that which is unlimited can
never be contained in that which is limited." But in ash-Shafi'i's use of analogy
there is a distinction to be observed. In seeking to establish a parallelism between a
case that has arisen and a rule in the Qur'an or usage, which is similar in some points
but not precisely parallel, are we to look to external points of resemblance, or may we go
further and seek to determine the reason (illa) lying behind the rule and from that
draw our analogy? The point seems simple enough and the early speculative jurists sought
the reason. For that they were promptly attacked by the traditionists. Such a method was
an attempt to look into the mysteries of God, they were told; man has no business to
inquire after reasons, all he has to do is to obey. The point thus raised was fought over
for centuries and schools are classified according to their attitude toward it. The
position of ash-Shafi'i seems to have been that the reason for a command was to be
considered in drawing an analogy, but that there must be some clear guide, in the text
itself, pointing to the reason. He thus left himself free to consider the causes of the
divine commands and yet produced the appearance of avoiding any irreverence or impiety in
doing so.
Such then are the four sources or bases (asls) of jurisprudence as accepted and
defined by ash-Shafi'iQur'an, prophetic usage, analogy, agreement. The
|
|