|
people of Spain, who were probably of stiffer orthodoxy than the Berbers. He was in
Spain, at Cordova, at the time, and was engaged in carrying on a religious war with the
Christians. On his return to Morocco the decree of exile was recalled and Ibn Rushd
restored to favor. We find him again at the court in Morocco, and he died there in 595.
This is not the place to enter upon Ibn Rushd's philosophical system. He was a
thorough-going Aristotelian, as he knew Aristotle. That was probably much better than any
of his predecessors; but even he had not got clear from the fatal influence of Plotinus.
Above all, he is essentially a theologian just as much as they. In Aristotle there had
been given what was to all intents a philosophical revelation. Only in the knowledge and
acceptance of it could truth and life be found. And some must reach it; one at least there
must always be. If a thing is not seen by someone it has existed in vain; which is
impossible. If someone at least does not know the truth, it also has existed in vain,
which is still more impossible. That is Ibn Rushd's way of saying that the esse is
the percipi and that there must be a perceiver. And he has unlimited faith in his
means of reaching that Truthonly by such capitalization can we express his theologic
attitude. The logic of Aristotle is infallible and can break through to the supreme good
itself. Ecstasy and contemplation play no part with him; there he separates from Ibn
Tufayl. Such intercourse with the Active Intellect may exist; but it is too rare to be
taken into account. Obviously, Ibn Rushd himself, who to himself was
|
|
ATTACK ON AL-GHAZZALI
|
257 | |
the percipient of truth for his age, had never reached that perception. Solitary
meditation he cannot away with; for him the market-place and contact with men; there he
parts with Ibn Bajja. In truth, he is nearer to the life in life of Ibn Sina, and that,
perhaps, explains his constant attacks on the Persian bon vivant.
All his predecessors he joys in correcting, but his especial bete noire is al-Ghazzali.
With him it is war on life or death. He has two good causes. One is al-Ghazzali's
"Destruction of the Philosophers;" of it, Ibn Rushd, in his turn, writes a
"Destruction." This is a clever, incisive criticism, luminous with logical
exactitude, yet missing al-Ghazzali's vital earnestness and incapable of reaching his
originality. But al-Ghazzali had not only attacked the philosophers; he had also spread
the knowledge of their teachings and reasonings, and had said that there was nothing
esoteric and impossible of grasp in them for the ordinary mind. He had thus assailed the
fundamental principles of the Muwahhid system. Against this, Ibn Rushd wrote the tractates
spoken of above. They were evidently addressed to the educated laity; not to the ignorant
multitude, but to those who had already read such books as those of al-Ghazzali and been
affected by them, yet had not studied philosophy at firsthand. That they were not intended
for such special students is evident from the elaborate care that is taken in them to
conceal, or, if that were not possible, to put a good face upon obnoxious doctrines. Thus,
his philosophy left no place in reality for a system of rewards and punishments or even
for
|
|